2.63 Speech Acts

Category: Philosophy of Language

Keywords: illocutionary, hearer, utterances, conversation, utterance, grice, speech, austin, audience, speaker, uttered, assertions, assertion, communication, contextual

Number of Articles: 252
Percentage of Total: 0.8%
Rank: 63rd

Weighted Number of Articles: 250.8
Percentage of Total: 0.8%
Rank: 67th

Mean Publication Year: 1986.1
Weighted Mean Publication Year: 1981.8
Median Publication Year: 1986
Modal Publication Year: 1971

Topic with Most Overlap: Ordinary Language (0.0647)
Topic this Overlaps Most With: Sense and Reference (0.0328)
Topic with Least Overlap: Evolutionary Biology (0.00051)
Topic this Overlaps Least With: Egalitarianism (0.00042)

Speech Acts

Figure 2.143: Speech Acts

Speech Acts Articles in Each Journal

Figure 2.144: Speech Acts Articles in Each Journal

Comments

This graph, on the other hand, represents a story that I was in the right place at the right time to see first hand. It’s a very distinctively shaped graph. I don’t think any of the other 89 have a peak, then a steep dip, then a second wave, quite like this.

The story behind it is I think fairly well known by now. Austin developed speech act theory in the 1950s, but the key ideas didn’t really get picked up until well into the 1960s. Then the story was developed more by Searle and others, and for a while it looked like a really promising approach to thinking about a number of puzzling features of language. But in part because the early promise didn’t seem to be being realised, and in part because it was overtaken by Kripkean and Montagovian approaches, it started to feel like a superseded research program. (And maybe there is a connection here to the Linguistics Wars (Harris 1995), but I don’t really know how much they impacted the philosophy journals at all.) So by the 1980s and early 1990s it was looking like yet another mid-century research program that had once been quite prominent in the journals, but now wasn’t.

Except at Monash it didn’t look like that at all. Rather, it looked like speech act theory provided the key tools for developing and explaining a really interesting, and provocative, theory of communication that one of our newest faculty members was building. It was an interesting enough theory that you could hear people talking about illocutionary and perlocutionary effects in between planning parties in the student union. It felt like if this caught on, then speech act theory wasn’t a superseded research program at all, but something that was essential to understand if you wanted to understand the role of language in human society.

It caught on.

That new junior faculty member is now the Knightbridge Professor of Philosophy at Cambridge, and her work, along with the work of other important feminist philosophers, has transformed our understanding of speech acts. And it is responsible for one of the only second acts in analytic philosophy, as speech act theory itself went from being on the path to obsolenence to a central place in philosophical theorising.