Philosophy 361 Ethics Darwall Fall 1997 METAETHICS III: IDEAL JUDGMENT THEORIES TAP Assignment for 10/6: Ayer, pp. 78-79 (esp. para. 6) I According to the ideal judge theory, what it is for something to be good or bad, or for an act to be right or wrong, is for it to be the case that an ideal judge would regard the thing or act in a certain way. The underlying idea is that we can identify qualities of good judgment independently of normative views about what sorts of things are good or right. Think of people whose ethical judgment you trust. Aren't they: (i) well-informed about the issues in question; (ii) experienced, sensitive, and able to imagine vividly what it is like "from the inside" for persons and creatures who are likely to be affected in the issue in question; (iii) dispassionate and judicious, and form their attitudes by trying to temper momentary emotions like anger, envy, and so on. (iv) impartial, likely to view the issues, not from their own personal standpoint. These are general epistemological virtues. But a more radical possibility has had substantial philosophical appeal in ethics, viz., there is no truth, independent of what would issue from good judgment, that the ideal judge is better able to track. Rather, ethical beliefs are true if, and only if, they would be held by an ideal observer. This is what ethical truth consists in. Call this idea the ideal observer, or ideal judge, theory. II So far we only have a sketch of a theory. (i) What is the full specification of the features characterizing the ideal judge? (ii) What is the way (or ways) of regarding things, such that when held by the ideal judge, they determine value and obligation? A. Take (ii) first. What if we say that something's being intrinsically good is the same thing as its being thought to be intrinsically good by an ideal judge. Is this circularity a problem? What is the content of the ideal judge's thought? Do we face an infinite regress? There may not be a problem if we are not attempting a conceptual reduction. Maybe we can understand what it is to regard something as intrinsically good, and the question is the metaphysical one of what it is to be intrinsically good. B. Another reductionist possibility: something is intrinsically good if, and only if, an ideal judge would prefer (desire) it (i.e. its existence to its nonexistence). Does this theory remind you of Mill? This may work fairly well for intrinsic goodness, but what about moral rightness? What sort of way of regarding things, held by the ideal judge, can determine that? We might say that an act is wrong if it would be disapproved of by an ideal judge. But is their a way of understanding what disapproval is without understanding what wrong is? Thus, compare disapproval of an act of betrayal with the sort of dislike one might have for a joke that was really corny. Is there any way of capturing the difference in response, except to say that in the case of disapproval, one thinks that a wrong has been done. If there is not, then we seem to be back faced with the problem mentioned in II.A. above. C. The other set of problems with the view concern giving a fuller specification of the ideal judge. Take the features (i)-(iv). The problem is that they do not seem to determine a unique set of judgments. Thus, compare two different judges who come from two quite different societies--one comes from a society that has a culture of machismo and masculine codes of honor, the other comes from a society that stresses maintaining harmonious relationships and turning the other cheek. Is it not true that if we were to endow both with complete knowledge, impartiality, experience, and dispassionateness we might still get different judgments, for example, with respect to how it is appropriate to respond to an insult? The ideal judge from the first society might disapprove of failing to challenge the offender, whereas the ideal judge from the latter might disapprove of such a challenge, approving, rather, of attempts to conciliate. (i) One response to this problem would be to be a sort of relativism. (ii) Another response would be to try to specify the characteristics of the ideal judge further. Adam Smith and David Hume argued that an ideal judge would be equally sympathetic with the interests of all individuals. It is not coincidental that these writers had broadly utilitarian sensibilities. Critics of utilitarianism will object that this theory already begs the question in the direction of utilitarianism. III The ideal judge theory might have substantial appeal if it can overcome these problems. It seems to be a kind of naturalistic theory, but one that might be able to escape some of the problems that afflict other naturalistic theories. (i) the features that realize the ideal, are natural features: being informed, being dispassionate, being experienced, and being impartial, even if they are not realizable in the limit, or ideally, in nature. In this way they are like an ideal gas in chemistry, a frictionless surface in physics, or a perfect market in economics. We may still regard our theory about what an ideal judge would think as a theory about nature, in some suitably broad sense. (ii) on the other hand, unlike other naturalistic theories, it may be able to respond to some of the criticisms of ethical naturalism. Consider, for example, the objection that naturalism cannot capture the normative or recommending force of ethical judgments, since they simply describe reality, whereas ethical judgments seem to endorse or condemn it in some respect or other. According to the ideal judge theory, there is a truth about, say, something's intrinsic goodness, just in case an ideal judge, or, to put more generously, oneself were one judging ideally, would endorse or prefer the existence of that thing.