Philosophy 361 Ethics Darwall Fall 1997 META-ETHICS I: NATURALISM I Recall the distinction made in the first lecture between metaethics and normative ethics. Roughly: Normative ethics concerns questions like: What is good? What is right? What is the test of right and wrong? Metaethics concerns philosophical issues about ethics. What is goodness or value? II We can put one basic metaphysical issues in the form of a dilemma. A. From the inside, ethical convictions purport to be objective. Compare, for example, the belief that it is wrong to cause gratuitous harm to innocents, with a preference for a flavor of ice cream. These seem different. When people disagree about the latter, they can see this as disagreement in taste, but not in the former case. If someone were to judge that there is nothing wrong in harming innocents, we are likely to think this judgment is mistaken. Note that this doesn't mean that we think ourselves infallible. To the contrary. The issue of fallibility doesn't even arise in matters of brute difference of taste. It is because our ethical judgments purport to be true that we can take seriously the possibility that we are mistaken. B. On the other hand, it can be hard to see what could make ethical beliefs true or false, what their truth or falsity could consist in. Harman raises this problem in the following way. Harman's Problem. In science, we confirm theories by seeing whether their predictions correspond to experience. If we observe what the theory predicts, we take this as evidence for the theory. This might already seem a contrast with ethics. What functions as observations in ethics? Why not intuitive ethical convictions? We might think that this differs from science because intuitive ethical judgments are already "infected" with theory. But neither is it the case in science that observations are "theory neutral." The real probem, Harman says, is that there is a further difference. In science we take not just what we observe, but also our observing it, to be explained by the theory, and this gives us reason to take our observation as evidence for the truth of the theory. Harman's challenge: nothing like this is true in ethics. Examples III Fundamental Dilemma of Metaethics: Either ethical convictions can be true (as they seem from the inside) or they cannot be. If they can, what can make them true? In what does their truth consist? If they cannot be, then why do we think, feel, and talk as though they can? IV NATURALISM. One response to these issues is naturalism. The ethical naturalist holds that ethical propositions can indeed be true, and that is because ethical properties are themselves really natural properties. What properties are natural properties? Most uncontroversially, any that we can discover by empirical investigation. There are basically two kinds of naturalist position: reductive naturalism and nonreductive naturalism. Reductive naturalism holds that ethical properties are identical to properties that can be identified with the vocabulary of the empirical sciences or empircal "folk theory". For example, the position that value is the property of being desired. Would be a form of reductive naturalism. Nonreductive naturalism holds that ethical properties are natural, even though they can't be "reduced" to those identifiable through other such vocabularies. It may be that ethical properties can only be referred to be ethical terms, but nonetheless be true that ethical properties are natural properties. Question: Is Mill a naturalist? If so, what sort is he? Faced with Harman's contrast above, one tack open to the naturalist is to hold that value and morality are real aspects of the world that really do explain things. Thus, the naturalist might say, our ethical convictions may indeed be explained by the (natural) ethical facts. The challenge is to make this position plausible. V A problem for naturalism advanced by G. E. Moore's Principia Ethica (1903):. Take any natural property you please--e.g., being desired or being pleasant. It would seem that there could still be a dispute between two individuals who agree that a thing has that property, but disagree about whether it is good. What is this dispute about? If it is really about whether the thing is good, then goodness apparently cannot be the same as the natural property we initially took, since there is no dispute about whether the thing has that property. So, the arugment concludes, ethical naturalism is false. Goodness is not any aspect of nature. [n.b. if this argument works, it presumably also works against the idea that goodness is a supernatural property.] ***************************************************************** ***** Text Analysis Project Assignment for 10/1: Harman, NM, pp. 41-46. ***************************************************************** *****