CONTRACTUALISM: RAWLS’S JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS Moral Conversation Project for next time: In “The Case for Animal Rights,” Tom Regan presents some criticisms of a contractualist or “contractarian” approach in light of its treatment of the rights of animals (B, 111-112). Peter Carruthers defends a contractualist approach to this issue (B, 127-133). Who do you think has the better of this debate and why? I. Utilitarianism and Libertarianism as competing conceptions of moral equality. A. Utilitarianism: Everyone’s happiness matters equally. Everyone is owed equal consideration of his or her interests (happiness). B. Libertarianism: Everyone has an equal dignity or moral status, consisting in having equal negative rights to life, liberty, and property. II Rawls’s contractualism offers a different conception of moral equality. A. Morality as a system of norms for a community of free and equal persons. 1. The norms structure a community of equals—they give everyone equal status and express respect for this equal status. 2. The norms are themselves subject to the agreement (consent) of free and equal persons. (Note the difference with Locke: For Locke, norms granting equal moral rights are assumed as given, and political laws are subject to consent. For contractualism, even moral norms are derived from the consent of free persons.) B. Comparison and contrast with Libertarianism and Utilitarianism 1. Like Libertarianism, Contractualism sees human beings as having equal moral status by virtue of their being persons, i.e., their capacity for independent moral responsibility and agency. Note the difference with Utilitarianism here. What is morally considerable is not pleasure or happiness, but the capacity of moral action. 2. But unlike Libertarianism, and like Utilitarianism, Contractualism doesn’t assume a fixed set of natural rights as fundamental and self-evident. Rather it derives specific rights (e.g. of liberty, property, etc.) from what rights free persons would agree or consent to. And, also like Utilitarianism, it maintains that the consequences of the social acceptance of a right are relevant here. Roughly: a right exists if a free and equal person would consent to the consequences of the social acceptance of that right. II. Justice as Fairness A. Strictly speaking, Rawls’s theory is a theory of justice. B. Roughly speaking, his idea is that society is a set of rule-structured practices and institutions, and that the rules (and the society) is fair and just if its most basic rules could be chosen by individuals in a situation (the original position) which is itself fair and just. C. The original position: 1. Individuals choose principles the will guide evaluation of 2. the “basic structure” of the society in which they will live. 3. They choose behind a “veil of ignorance” regarding their own social position, talents, and interests, 4. but choose principles likeliest to put them in the best person to pursue their interests, whatever they happen to be. D. Therefore, the “principles of justice” are whichever principles would be so chosen, i.e. would be chosen to guide social criticism of the basic structure of society from a position of equality (i.e., in the original position, behind the veil of ignorance.) III. Rawls’s Two Principles of Justice A. Their content 1. Equal basic liberty principle: Everyone has certain basic rights: right to life, equal political participation, free speech, free thought, and right to acquire property (but not unrestricted, as libertarianism holds). 2. Difference principle: other benefits and burdens (e.g. wealth) must be distributed so that they work to the greatest advantage of the least advantaged. (I.e., the minimum position must be maximized) B. Rawls’s argument that his two principles, rather than either libertarianism or utilitarianism would be chosen from the original position.