ARGUMENTS AGAINST AFFIRMATIVE ACTION I. Arguments for AA from last time: A. Natural Rights Theory (Backward-Looking): AA as compensation for systematic, governmentally-condoned violations of Lockean rights. B. (Forward-looking) consequentialist (utilitarian) arguments: AA as necessary to advance such ends as (greater equality, a more diverse society, a workforce better trained to deal with an increasingly diverse society and international economy. C. Contractualism. 1. AA as necessary to achieve fair equality of opportunity. (To make life chances more closely match native talents.) 2. AA as necessary to prepare students to participate as equal citizens in political debate and decision-making. II. The “simple” argument against AA. 1. It is unjust to discriminate against individuals because of their race. 2. AA discriminates against individuals because of their race. 3. Therefore, AA is unjust. III. Problems with the “simple” argument. A. As we ordinarily use the phrase ‘discriminate against,” is by definition unjust to discriminate against someone (on any basis that counts as “discrimination against”). Consequently, simply to assert that discrimination on the basis of race is discrimination against is question-begging. B. Suppose, we change the simple argument to: 1’. It is unjust to discriminate on the basis of race. 2’. AA discriminates on the basis of race. 3’. Therefore, AA is unjust. C. 1’, the leading premise, seems very plausible. After all, isn’t racial discrimination what proponents of AA think is the injustice that, as they sometimes argue, calls for AA as compensation? Doesn’t that make AA reverse discrimination? And if so, how can two wrongs make a right? D. How can proponents of AA respond to this line of argument? 1. It is question-begging to assert that discriminating on the basis of race is always unjust, since that is just the point at issue. 2. Moreover, what was unjust about the previous racial injustices to which AA responds is not that they taking race into account, but that they did so in a way that either a. systematically subjugated, b. excluded, c. or stigmatized (or some combination of these) 3. Does AA do any of these? E. This suggests that critics of AA will have to buttress the “simple” argument. How might they do so? IV. A promising strategy might be to consider various arguments that proponents have given for AA and argue that, not only do these not justify AA, but that, when combined with a more careful look at social, political, economic, and historical data, they can be shown to argue against AA. V. For example, consider the backward-looking argument (what Scalia calls the “restorative argument”). 1. Blacks, as a group, have historically suffered substantial systematic violation of (Lockean) natural rights. 2. Victims of rights violations acquire a right to compensation. 3. AA programs are one way of fulfilling this right. A. Scalia argues that taking this argument seriously would require us to: 1. Identify other groups who are also entitled to compensation for substantial systematic violation of rights. 2. Identify relative-responsibility of groups with current members for these violations and, consequently, the degree of obligation to provide compensation. B. Such a “Restorative Justice Handicapping System” would then give each individual an AA score, either positive or negative. And such a system, he argues, would be “thoroughly offensive.” Assume for the moment this is correct. Presently, we will consider what, if anything, would be offensive about such a system. VI. How might proponents of AA respond to this argument? They might argue that the argument does not generalize in the ways that Scalia proposes. A. As regards the first point (V.A.1), they might argue that forced emigration, slavery, the “social death” (and political death) of deprivation of the status of citizen, and the more violent remnants of slavery in our society, make the case of race different. B. As regards the second point (V.A.2), they might argue that we shouldn’t think of the obligation to compensate as borne by the descendents of individual perpetrators, but rather by the society as a whole. VII. One reply that critics of AA might make to these responses is that even if they work in theory, they don’t in practice, since: A. As Sowell claims, it is politically difficult to keep AA narrowly circumscribed. Historically (and viewed internationally) AA programs tend to expand in scope, to take in more groups. B. AA programs tend to be viewed as an attempt to make descendants of the perpetrators compensate descendants of the victims—reverse stigma. VIII. Now consider forward-looking arguments. Here critics of AA argue that: A. AA fails to have the good consequences that are claimed on its behalf. B. AA has further, unintended bad consequences. IX. As regards the claimed benefits of AA, critics argue: A. Blacks who are most disadvantaged have not been helped (even superficially) by AA. Indeed, they have been hurt. The growth of the black underclass was coincident with growth in AA. B. Even blacks who appear to benefit by AA, don’t get real educational benefits. 1. The educational system does not hold them to the same standards, so they are less likely to hold themselves to these standards. 2. They are, on average, placed in educational environments that are inappropriate for their level of skills and preparation. X. Moreover, critics argue that AA also has the following bad consequences. A. It creates a “spoils system,” in which groups contend for benefits rather than individuals being evaluated on their merits. B. It adds to group conflict. C. It creates increasing cynicism, as academic decisions are believed to be driven by politics. D. It undermines the initiative of both those who benefit and those who don’t. E. It perpetuates ways of categorizing people, including the very concept of race, which are inherently unjust. F. It